The Ideology of Dialogue
The situationists practice of concretely breaking with apologists for any aspect of
the present social order (particularly visible with regard to the leading
representatives of the culture and politics of submission, and including as its
extreme case the exclusion of certain members of the SI) has been subject to the greatest
misunderstanding, although it follows quite directly from our basic positions. Certain
commentators have propagated the most hostile interpretations of this practice, thereby
causing concern among semi-informed people. The reality in this particular case is quite
simple. Those who accept one or more variants of the prevailing pseudodialogue become the
advocates of a new type of free exchange in the name of an abstract right to
dialogue at any price (payable in avowed concessions to falsehood), and they reproach us
for interrupting this fake dialogue. It is, however, only in this way that we are
able to be the bearers of the reality of dialogue. On the question of exclusion, we
believe that through experimentation we have made an advance in determining the
requirements for the nonhierarchical organization of joint projects, which
projects can be sustained only by the self-discipline of individuals proving themselves in
the coherence of the theories and acts through which each member strives to merit his
joint responsibility with all the others. The one-sidedness of Stirners notions on
the relations of the egoist with the organization that he enters or leaves at whim (though
it does contain a kernel of truth regarding that aspect of freedom) does
not allow any independent basis for his passive and defenseless ghost of an
organization. Such an incoherent and undisciplined organization is at the
mercy of any individual egoist, who can cynically exploit it for his own ends
while disdaining any social aims it might have (and in fact the Stirnerian individual can
just as well enter the most reactionary association for his own personal profit). But a
free association a bond, not a power(1) in which several
individuals meet on a common basis cannot be passively subject to someones
individual whim. Those who wish neither to judge nor to command must be able to reject
any person whose conduct would implicate them. When the SI excludes someone, we are
calling him to account not for his life but for ours, for the common
project that he would falsify (whether out of hostile intentions or through mere lack of
discernment). Each side remains individually free (the fact that this freedom is generally
impoverished is another problem, without which there would be no need for undertakings
like the SI), and by throwing back on his own an individual who has always remained
autonomous we are only expressing the fact that this autonomy was not able to fulfill
itself within our common project. In rejecting someone in accordance with the rules of the
game that he thought he had accepted, or had pretended to accept, it is our own
resignation that we are rejecting.
It may be helpful to elucidate these remarks with excerpts from two letters recently addressed to one of our correspondents in East Europe.(2)
(First letter.) Our theoretical positions (on play, language, etc.) would not only risk becoming mendacious and valueless, they would already be without value if we held them in coexistence with some doctrinal dogmatism, whatever it might be. All of us believe, as you do, that the freedom to travel all the unaccustomed paths must be absolute (and not only on the artistic or theoretical plane, but in all aspects of practical life). For a thousand reasons, of which the experience of the Eastern bloc is the most obvious, we know that an ideology in power turns any partial truth into an absolute lie. . . . We are not a power in society, and thus our exclusions only express our freedom to distinguish ourselves from the confusionism around us or even among us, which confusionism is much closer to the actual social power and partakes of all its benefits. We have never wished to prevent anyone from expressing their ideas or doing what they want (and we have never sought to be in a position to exert such pressure). We merely refuse to be ourselves mixed up with ideas and acts that run contrary to our convictions and tastes. Note that this is all the more vital in that we have hardly any freedom to express our own convictions and tastes, due to their going so sharply against the mainstream. Our intolerance is nothing but a very limited response to the very strict intolerance and exclusion that we run into everywhere, particularly among the intellectual establishment (considerably more intense than the hostility the surrealists had to endure), and which we scarcely find surprising. Just as we are in no degree a controlling power in society, we refuse to become one someday by means of some political reshuffling (we are in this regard partisans of radical self-management, of workers councils abolishing all separate state power or even separate theoretical power); and we are refusing to transform ourselves into any power whatsoever, even on the small scale that we would be allowed, when we refuse to enlist disciples, who would give us, along with the right of control and direction over themselves, a greater recognized social standing as representatives of one more artistic or political ideology. . . . One should not confuse the practical conditions of free thought here and in the East or in Spain, for example. In countries where nothing can be openly expressed, it is obviously necessary to support the right of everyone to express themselves. But in places where everyone can express themselves (though under conditions of enormous inequality) any radical thought without of course wishing to suppress this practical freedom must first of all clear the way for its own unaccustomed path, must assert its own right to exist without being coopted and distorted by the social order which manifestly reigns behind this visible confusion and complexity and which ultimately possesses the monopoly of appearances (see our critique of the spectacle in the consumer society of commodity abundance). Finally, the reigning tolerance is one-way, and this on a global scale in spite of the antagonisms and complexity of the different types of exploitive societies. What the tolerant people who are in a position to express themselves tolerate, fundamentally, is the established power everywhere. You tell us that you live in X... If you were in Paris you would see how many of these tolerant leftist intellectuals turn out to be undecided, understanding, and tolerant toward the established conditions in X... or in Beijing. What they call the sense of history is their Hegelian adherence to what they read in the daily papers.
(Second letter.) A radically different point of departure in fact first of all restores the truth of the liberatory endeavors of the past. It is necessary to break clearly with the old confusion, and therefore with its partisans, whether they be open, cunning, or simply unconscious. We obviously have to bear the negative consequences of the attitude we have chosen, and we have to acknowledge this negativity. . . . We are in complete agreement with you on the interrelation of all aspects of the problem of the present avant-garde. We are in fact trying to initiate dialogue everywhere that that state of mind manifests itself in a radical direction. For that state of mind is itself divided by a struggle between its truth and its organized cooption by the ruling powers.
SITUATIONIST INTERNATIONAL
1966
TRANSLATOR’S NOTES
1. “a bond, not a power”: Marx’s characterization of the First International.
2. The correspondent was Branko
Vucicovic in Prague. The full text of the two letters can be found in Guy Debords Correspondance
(Volume 3, pp. 89-92 and 115-117).
Lidéologie du dialogue
originally appeared in Internationale Situationniste #10 (Paris, March
1966). This translation by Ken Knabb is from the
Situationist
International Anthology (Revised and Expanded Edition, PM Press, 2024). No copyright.